Some Strategies for Handling Gettier Problems
An Introduction to Epistemology pp. 65-82
Goal: Amend the JTB (Justified True Belief) analysis so that we can preclude Gettier-type (wrong evidence for a belief) cases.
- There are 3 proposals. We need to look for an âanalysis that ties our justification more closely to the truth of the belief, such that it is less of an accident that the belief turns out true, given the evidence the agent hasâ (66) which is also known as « the accidentality problem »
Proposals:
- Causal Theories
- This theory involves a subtly different understanding of the justification condition, shifting from âevidentialâ to âcausalâ sense of justification.
- A belief is an instance of knowledge if the belief is true and is caused in the right way⊠i.e. The target belief is the causal result of reasons (other beliefs).
- Example: You believe that there is coffee in the mug because when you look over there is a mug, and it contains coffee. Your belief is true because there is coffee in the mug.
- Goldman states, âS knows that p IFF the fact p is causally connected in an âappropriateâ way with Sâs believing p.â (68) ⊠what is appropriate?
- An appropriate process is a causal chain using perception, memory, and/or inference.
- Problem: One can be led to infer that the cause of Xâs death is an apparent death wound, but in reality, X was poisoned.
- âEvidentialâ vs âCausalâ Justification:
- âConsider again the belief that there is coffee in the cup. Clearly, a causal connection exists between agent and cup, namely, perception. In the causal view, the fact of this connection is enough to justify the agentâs belief; there is a reason for the agentâs belief. In the evidential sense of reason, however, for the agent to be justified, the existence of this causal connection is not enough. The agent must also, at the very least believe that this connection existsâ (69)
- This theory involves a subtly different understanding of the justification condition, shifting from âevidentialâ to âcausalâ sense of justification.
- Indefeasibility Theories
- Indefeasible justification is one for which there is no undermining evidence.
- i.e. there exists no other evidence such as that, if revealed, the justification would be undermined (very strong condition).
- Undermining evidence is also called defeating evidence.
- A justification is defeasible IFF there is defeating evidence.
- Thus, âthe sort of justification required for knowledge is not simply [JTB] but also indefeasible justificationâ (69)
- Question: how to guarantee that there is no defeating evidence?
- âIndefeasibility theorists do not require that an agent be able to show that there are no defeaters. Nor do they require that the agent believe there are no defeaters. Rather, for a justification to be indefeasible, these theorists require merely that there in fact be no defeaters. Whether this fact is reflected in the agentâs beliefs makes no difference to the defeasibility of the agentâs justificationâ (71) ⊠surprised Pikachu face what is the point then ??
- Genuine vs Misleading âDefeatersâ Problem:
- Example: You come to believe that planet earth is spherical. You saw the pictures, heard scientists talk about it, and read plenty of convincing evidence. One day, a video of the âPope of Scienceâ circles around where he states, âEarth is flat, and those NASA conspirators are brainwashing the public.â That might sound like a âdefeaterâ at first glance, however, you were unaware that the video was actually a deepfake
- Misleading defeaters are defeaters that can themselves be defeated to ârestoreâ the original justification.
- Indefeasible justifications must be able to withstand the acquisition of new information.
- Robert Meyers: âWhat protects your knowledge is not the original justification but the fact that you learned the counterevidence along with the evidence that nullifies itâ (73).
- Response: âthe indefeasibility theorist might suggest the following: a justification need not include evidence sufficient to rule out misleading defeaters; it is only necessary that the agent could acquire that evidence without changing or giving up the beliefs that comprised the original justificationâ (74).
- Practical Issues:
- Difficult to find a way to amend the JTB analysis that distinguishes between genuine and misleading defeaters.
- The condition may be too strong and rule out legitimate cases of inductive knowledge.
- If the condition is weaker, it may fail to distinguish between defective and merely incomplete justifications.
- Indefeasible justification is one for which there is no undermining evidence.
- No-False-Premise Views (a 4th-condition approach)
- Fourth condition: the justification does not depend on any false premises.
- Too strong. What if some false premise is not essential to the justification?
- âThe agent would not be justified in believing that P unless the agent also believed some further proposition Q. The proposition Q is then said to be essential to the agentâs justificationâ (75).
- Meyersâ fourth condition: âS is justified in believing p on the basis of q only if: every proposition essential to S being justified in believing p on the basis of q is trueâ (76).
- Feldmanâs Objection (Explicit vs Implicit false premise): if S had seen Nogot driving a Ford and S had been told that Nogot owned a Ford, and had immediately inferred that someone in the office owned a Ford, then Sâs justification would not depend on a false premise.
- Response: whether S articulates or reasons explicitly from a false proposition, S clearly seems to believe something false (that Nogot owns a Ford)⊠but how to decide which âbackground beliefsâ are essential to the explicit belief?
- Fourth condition: the justification does not depend on any false premises.
Significance of Gettier:
- Two main issues: (a) the nature of knowledge (b) the nature of justification
- As it stands, roughly, the 3 proposals present JTB as necessary, if not sufficient, for knowledge.
- It is possible to avoid the Gettier issue? There seems to be a gap between the satisfaction of the justification condition and the satisfaction of the truth condition.
- Ernest Sosa suggested that âknowledge is apt (true) beliefâ (77).
- simple perceptual beliefs vs complicated chain of inductive reasoning
- Mark Kaplan hinted, in an article, that âItâs Not What You Know That Counts.â
- The environment has deceived the agent, but what can the agent do?
- Gettier cases suggest that âwe can have knowledge only in a generally cooperative environment. If we rely on our generally âaccredited routes to knowledge,â we count on the world being more or less normalâ (79) ⊠true, we are âluckyâ the world is sensible
Accounts of knowledge and Justification (79):
- Externalism: roughly the idea that an agentâs justification or knowledge depends on some condition that need not be reflected in an agentâs beliefs
- Internalism: roughly holds that a belief is justified only if the relevant justifying conditions are in some respect reflected in the agentâs beliefs or cognitive perspective.
- âThe causal theory does not appear to insist that knowledge depends on the reasons for which an agent holds the belief. This has led some to think that knowledge is externalist in nature, while justification is internalistâ (79).
Foleyâs Take (80):
- âIn asking whether a person knows, we are asking whether, relative to the âneighborhoodâ of the target belief, the person has sufficient true beliefs.â
- Connection between knowledge and justified belief is âdubious.â
- It is difficult to identify the relevant âneighborhoodâ (context) of a target belief, but Foley suggests that is true of any account of knowledge.
- âFoley further suggests that externalists are principally interested in knowledge, while internalists are principally concerned about the nature of justification.â
- This marks the âbeginning of the division between internalist and externalist conceptions of knowledge and justification.â
This post is licensed under CC BY 4.0 by the author.